The Figure of Nature: On Greek Origins

The Figure of Nature: On Greek Origins

by John Sallis
The Figure of Nature: On Greek Origins

The Figure of Nature: On Greek Origins

by John Sallis

eBook

$13.49  $17.99 Save 25% Current price is $13.49, Original price is $17.99. You Save 25%.

Available on Compatible NOOK devices, the free NOOK App and in My Digital Library.
WANT A NOOK?  Explore Now

Related collections and offers

LEND ME® See Details

Overview

One of America’s preeminent philosophers “has produced a book with fascinating new insights into the ancient conception of nature” (Choice).

Broaching an understanding of nature in Platonic thought, John Sallis goes beyond modern conceptions and provides a strategy to have recourse to the profound sense of nature operative in ancient Greek philosophy. In a rigorous and textually based account, Sallis traces the complex development of the Greek concept of nature. Beginning with the mythical vision embodied in the figure of the goddess Artemis, he reanimates the sense of nature that informs the fragmentary discourses of Anaximenes, Heraclitus, Parmenides, and Empedocles and shows how Plato takes up pre-Socratic conceptions critically while also being transformed. Through Sallis’s close reading of the Theaetetus and the Phaedo, he recovers the profound and comprehensive concept of nature in Plato’s thought.

Product Details

ISBN-13: 9780253023360
Publisher: Indiana University Press
Publication date: 03/04/2020
Series: Studies in Continental Thought
Sold by: Barnes & Noble
Format: eBook
Pages: 263
Sales rank: 901,584
File size: 902 KB
Age Range: 18 Years

About the Author

<P>John Sallis is Frederick J. Adelmann Professor of Philosophy at Boston College. He is author of more than 20 books, including Light Traces (IUP, 2014) and Logic of Imagination (IUP, 2012).</P>

Read an Excerpt

The Figure of Nature

On Greek Origins


By John Sallis

Indiana University Press

Copyright © 2016 John Sallis
All rights reserved.
ISBN: 978-0-253-02336-0



CHAPTER 1

THE REIGN OF ARTEMIS


She reigned with such sovereignty that her rule extended even into the beginning of the Christian era. It is reported that when Paul came to Ephesus, the site of the great temple of Artemis, he encountered such resistance that he dared not enter the theatre where the Ephesians were assembled. A surrogate named Alexander was thus put forth to offer a defense to the multitude assembled there. Yet when the crowd recognized that he was affiliated with Paul, then "for about two hours they all with one voice cried out 'Great is Artemis of the Ephesians!'"

Her reign extended throughout Greece, from Ephesus, Miletus, and Samos, the three sites where what would be called philosophy had its beginning, to the Greek mainland and on beyond to Magna Graecia. In the [TEXT NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII] recounting the deeds through which she exercised her sovereignty, her bond to [TEXT NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII], to what would come to be called nature, was paramount. In this [TEXT NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII] the figure of nature was already drawn before philosophy came onto the scene and set about interrogating nature as such. When philosophy appeared on the scene, it took up this figure in which a certain sense of nature was already gathered. Even though the name Artemis goes largely unmentioned by the early Greek thinkers, the disclosure of nature sustained by her [TEXT NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII] remained directive for Greek thought from its beginning on.

Homer calls her "Artemis of the wild, the mistress of wild beasts," thus declaring her reign in the sense both of her sovereignty, her rule, and of the domain over which she rules, her kingdom or realm. She may seem to be a kind of goddess of nature, and yet, at best, the genitive expression only defers a proper characterization of the bond between Artemis and nature, of the manner in which she carries out her reign. Her rule bears little resemblance to that of a human monarch: whereas a mortal queen will always be intent on displaying herself in all her glory before those whom she rules, Artemis, as a goddess, is never to be directly beheld. Even her most devout follower, Hippolytus, declares that he cannot see her face to face. Though indeed he has the unique privilege of hearing and answering to her words, for all other humans she appears only from within her realm, only in and through what she effects in the wild places over which she reigns, but in which, nonetheless, she remains withdrawn from the sight of mortals. Yet precisely as reigning — while remaining withdrawn — over the domain in which things are begotten and come to be born ([TEXT NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII]), Artemis is set apart as one who does not give birth. She is ayvq, pure, chaste. She is an inviolable virgin.

She reigns over the wild regions beyond the cities and beyond the cultivated fields. When her ardent disciple Hippolytus returns from her meadow and approaches her altar, he declares:

My Goddess Mistress, I bring you ready woven
this garland. It was I that plucked and wove it,
plucked it for you in your inviolate meadow.
No shepherd dares to feed his flock within it:
no reaper plies a busy scythe within it:
only the bees in springtime haunt the inviolate meadow.


Her reign takes two forms, which, though apparently opposed, are in fact intrinsically connected. First of all, she is a huntress. Vase paintings portray her as the beautiful virgin huntress clad in a short tunic and carrying a bow and a quiver of arrows; often she is accompanied by a stag or a doe. The Homeric Hymn dedicated to her describes her in these words: "I sing of Artemis, whose shafts are of gold, who cheers on the hounds, the pure maiden, shooter of stags, who delights in archery, sister to Apollo with the golden sword." Along with her twin brother, Apollo, she was born on the island of Delos, the daughter of Zeus and Leto. In the Odyssey there is a more extended portrayal of her, which provides the context in which the beautiful maiden Nausikaa is compared to her:

As Artemis, the archer, roves over the mountains,
along the ridges of Taygetus or on lofty Erymanthus,
delighting in the pursuit of boars and swift deer,
and the nymphs, daughters of Zeus who bears the aegis,
share her sport and Leto is glad at heart —
high above them all Artemis holds her head and brows,
and easily may she be known, though all are beautiful —
so this one shone among her handmaidens,
a virgin unwedded.


Ranging across Taygetus, a high range of mountains on the western border of Laconia, or climbing to the top of Erymanthus, a lofty mountain in Arcadia that was the haunt of the Erymanthean Boar, Artemis and her nymphs pursue their wild prey. Yet it is not only to wild beasts that she is a threat, not only at them that she aims her arrows, but also at women. The passage in the Iliad in which she is described as "Artemis of the wild, the mistress of wild beasts" tells of an episode in which she scolded her brother for having yielded in a quarrel with Poseidon. Though — as the account continues — Apollo said nothing in his defense, Hera, full of anger, set upon Artemis with these words:

It will be hard for you to match your strength with mine
even if you wear a bow, since Zeus has made you a lion
among women, and given you leave to kill any at your pleasure.
Better for you to hunt down the ravening beasts in the mountains
and deer of the wild, than try to fight in strength with your
betters.


Whatever the measure of her strength against the likes of Hera may be, Artemis is — by Zeus' decree — a lion among women, and as such she can inflict sudden death upon them with her golden arrows.

And yet, as she can bring death, so also can she offer protection to all creatures who are born and aid to those who bear them. She reigns not only as huntress among animals and lion among women, but also as one who gives succor to the young of wild beasts and comfort to women in childbirth.

In Aeschylus' Agamemnon the chorus sings of her reign:

Beautiful you are and kind
to the tender young ravening lions.
For sucklings of all the savage
beasts that lurk in the lonely places you have sympathy.


As protector of wild beasts, Artemis vents her anger when an animal is killed within her sanctuary. Especially loathsome to her is any slaying that interrupts the natural course of nativity. Thus the chorus tells also how her anger was provoked when a hare bearing its unborn young was killed and devoured.

In the story of how, on its way to Troy, the Hellenic fleet commanded by Agamemnon was detained at Aulis, Artemis is identified as the one responsible for summoning the strong contrary wind that prevented the ships from sailing on. When Agamemnon consulted Calchas the soothsayer, the words he heard announced that the ships would be allowed to sail only if Agamemnon's daughter Iphigenia were offered as a sacrifice to Artemis. There are at least two accounts of the reason this sacrifice was demanded by the goddess. One is found in Euripides' Iphigenia in Tauris. At the outset of the drama, Iphigenia herself repeats the words that were addressed to Agamemnon when he brought his inquiry to Calchas:

Agamemnon,
Captain of Hellas, there can be no way
of setting your ships free until the offering
you promised Artemis is given to her.
You had vowed to render in sacrifice to the light-bringing goddess
The most beautiful one born each year.


The sacrifice that is demanded by the goddess is to be carried out in belated fulfillment of a vow geared to natality. In this instance again what comes to light is the reign of the goddess over the domain of all that comes to be by way of birth, by being born ([TEXT NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII]), that is, the domain that also bears the name [TEXT NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII]. As her reign comes thus to light, she is herself given the epithet "light-bringing" ([TEXT NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII]).

The other account of Artemis' demand is found in Sophocles' Electra. The words are those of Electra, also a daughter of Agamemnon:

My father, as I hear, when at his sport,
started at his feet an antlered dappled stag
within the goddess' sanctuary. He
let fly and hit the deer and uttered some boast
about his killing of it. The daughter of Leto
was angry at this and therefore stayed the Greeks
in order that my father, to compensate
for the beast killed, might sacrifice his daughter.


As the protector of wild beasts, as the goddess who grants them the refuge in her sanctuary, Artemis demands recompense from anyone who, like Agamemnon, violates that sanctuary.

Powerless against the demand of the goddess, Agamemnon had wily Odysseus bring Iphigenia to Aulis under the false pretense that she was to marry Achilles before the fleet sailed. In Aeschylus' story of the events that followed, the sacrifice of Iphigenia was actually carried out. According to Euripides, however, she was snatched away at the last minute by Artemis, who substituted a deer for her. As she herself recounts it:

When I had come
to Aulis, they laid hands on me. The flame
was lit. The blow would have been struck — I saw
the knife. But Artemis deceived their eyes
with a deer to bleed for me and stole me through
the azure sky.


Borne off to Tauris, Iphegenia became Artemis' priestess, even — as some have declared — a second Artemis. Thus, in Euripides' version of the story, there is a peculiar reversal. Having demanded the sacrifice of Iphigenia, Artemis then becomes her protector, whisking her away from the scene of death to the sanctuary of Tauris, where as priestess she is entitled to deliver to mortals the words of the goddess. This reversal is indicative of just how intrinsically connected the two forms of Artemis' reign are.

Though a lion among women, Artemis was also often portrayed as coming to the aid of women, especially to those in childbirth. In such instances her intervention is not unlike that in the case of Iphigenia: at the very time when pain and the threat of death in childbirth are most intense, Artemis can be called on to bring aid and relief. Thus, in Hippolytus the chorus intones words that tell of the misery and helplessness of childbirth to which women are subject and of the aid that can be brought by Artemis:

My body, too, has felt this thrill of pain,
and I called on Artemis, queen of the bow;
she has my reverence always
as she goes in the company of the gods.


Artemis is the maieutic goddess who brings her reign to the confluence of pain and deliverance, of the threat of death and the promise of new life. She is the goddess whose name invokes the realm of [TEXT NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII] and who, herself unseen, reigns over all creatures that are born ([TEXT NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII]) and that accordingly belong to the domain of [TEXT NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII].

The two opposed directions in which Artemis exercises her sovereignty inscribe the primary lines around which the figure of nature takes shape. Her dual reign as both huntress and protector, as both demanding sacrifice and providing escape from it, and as both lion among women and comforter of those in childbirth mirrors in the figure of the goddess the ambivalent force of [TEXT NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII], that it both threatens and nurtures, that it both imposes deprivation and grants abundance, that it is the scene both of death and of new life.

Artemis is also light-bringing ([TEXT NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII]) and is portrayed as bearing torches in both hands. It is precisely as light-bringing that, in Euripides' dramatic presentation, she is promised the most beautiful one born each year. Yet the beauty, the radiance, the resplendence of one who, in being born, has come to behold the light of the sun can shine forth only in that light or, in its absence, by means of torches brought to light up the darkness. The light-bringing capacity of the goddess whose realm is [TEXT NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII] corresponds to the elemental bearing that light has in [TEXT NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII], that it is what allows all things to shine forth, each in its own distinctive way.

The word [TEXT NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII] commands to a large degree the writings of those whose thinking moves within the orbit of the beginning of philosophy. Indeed, in the formulation [TEXT NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII], it provided what is said to have been the title borne by many of these writings. According to the authors of late antiquity by whom what remains of these early Greek writings was transmitted, this title was used by Anaximander, Anaximenes, Xenophanes, Heraclitus, Zeno, and Empedocles. While it is not certain whether in all cases the title came from the authors themselves and not, rather, from Alexandrian editorial practices, its pervasiveness attests nonetheless to the prominence that discourse on [TEXT NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII] commanded in these writings. For those who wrote in proximity to the beginning of philosophy, the primary focus and animating theme of their thought was, with only few exceptions, [TEXT NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII]. Even later, when the venture is launched to set thinking apart from the beginning — as in Socrates' second sailing — [TEXT NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII] remains the reference point from which whatever might be projected beyond would be determined. Among the writings of the ancients, there are few that interrogate [TEXT NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII] so insistently as does the Theaetetus, despite — yet also perhaps because of — its critical detachment from almost all earlier writers from Homer to Empedocles.

Yet when early Greek thinking brings [TEXT NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII] into focus, it is its figure as already gathered in the figure of Artemis that is most readily discerned. In this regard the deeds of the thinker are most revelatory: to Heraclitus, above all, there are attributed deeds that reveal the bearing of the thinker who, precisely in his engagement with [TEXT NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII], is borne toward the goddess. Diogenes Laertius' report regarding Heraclitus' alleged book [TEXT NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII] is explicit: "He dedicated it in the temple of Artemis" (A1). The report also tells of how, convinced that his native city of Ephesus was governed by a bad constitution, Heraclitus refused to take part in writing laws and instead set himself entirely apart from the politics of his fellow citizens. In the words of the report: "Retiring into the temple of Artemis, he played knuckle-bones with children" (A1). Even though in Heraclitus' extant writings the name Artemis does not occur, the figure of the goddess sustained no doubt a certain openness to what came to be thought as [TEXT NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII]. Indeed, in the figuration of the goddess as remaining withdrawn from sight at the very scenes of her interventions, the Heraclitean declaration regarding the self-concealing propensity of [TEXT NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII] can already be discerned.

And yet, it is not as if the thinking of [TEXT NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII] simply leaves the figure of the goddess behind. More generally, it is not as if Greek thinking utterly abandons the mythic, simply forsaking whatever might have been given a degree of manifestness by it. The writings of Heraclitus and Empedocles abound with the names of the gods, of Zeus, Apollo, Aphrodite, and others; and these mythic names are closely configured with terms denoting moments seemingly remote from everything mythic, moments such as the natural elements or the recurrent cycles in nature. The Platonic dialogues are manifestly infused with mythic moments, with moments so thoroughly interwoven with the seemingly non-mythic [TEXT NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII] of the dialogues that they cannot be suppressed. Even when the portrayal of the Homeric gods is submitted to criticism, these figures continue to play a role in Platonic discourse, as do also such legendary figures as Theseus and Heracles. When, in the Phaedrus, Socrates is asked about such matters, the very formulation of the question incorporates the name of a mythic figure: "By Zeus, Socrates," says Phaedrus, "do you believe this mythic tale [[TEXT NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII]] to be true?" (229c). Though the question refers specifically to the tale of Boreas and Oreithyia, Socrates' response is more general. Ironically setting himself apart from those who explain away such tales, Socrates tells Phaedrus that he has no leisure ([TEXT NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII]) for such alleged explanations but rather accepts the current beliefs about them. Declaring that it would be ridiculous (laughable — [TEXT NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII]) to concern himself with devising such accounts when he does not yet know himself, he then goes on to describe the task of self-knowing by referring to a mythic figure and then finally to nature: "I investigate not these things but myself, to discover whether I am a monster more complicated and more furious than Typhon or a gentler and simpler animal to whom a divine and modest fate [povpa] is given by nature [[TEXT NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII]]" (230a). Thus, over against those who explain away mythic figures, Socrates describes his stance by invoking the mythic figure of Typhon, the hundred-headed monster who rose up against the gods and finally was killed by Zeus' thunderbolt. Though Socrates leaves undecided whether he belongs on the side of the monster or on the gentler side of nature, it is evident that mythic tales such as that of Typhon are woven into his discourse of self-knowing, and indeed that even monstrosity — that is, divergence from nature within nature — may have significant bearing on this endeavor.


(Continues...)

Excerpted from The Figure of Nature by John Sallis. Copyright © 2016 John Sallis. Excerpted by permission of Indiana University Press.
All rights reserved. No part of this excerpt may be reproduced or reprinted without permission in writing from the publisher.
Excerpts are provided by Dial-A-Book Inc. solely for the personal use of visitors to this web site.

Table of Contents

<P>Prologue<BR>1. The Reign of Artemis<BR>2. Open Air: On Philosophy before Philosophy<BR>3. Enshrouded Nature and the Fire of Heaven<BR>4. Radical Gatherings. The Imperative of Philosophy<BR>5. Monstrous Wonder. The Advance of Nature<BR>(a) Openings, Chronology, Topology<BR>(b) Appearings<BR>(c) Ventriloquy, the Protagorean, and the Scene of <BR>(d) The Scene of Philosophy<BR>(e) Parerga<BR>6. Earthbound. The Return of Nature<BR>(a) Theseus<BR>(b) Down to Earth<BR>(c) Mythologizing<BR>(d) Remembrance<BR>(e) Ascent<BR>(f) Second Sailing<BR>(g) Song of the Earth<BR>Index</P>
From the B&N Reads Blog

Customer Reviews