Phaedo

Phaedo

by Plato
Phaedo

Phaedo

by Plato

Paperback

$11.99 
  • SHIP THIS ITEM
    Qualifies for Free Shipping
  • PICK UP IN STORE
    Check Availability at Nearby Stores

Related collections and offers


Overview

Phaedo, also known to ancient readers as On The Soul, is one of the best-known dialogues of Plato's middle period, along with the Republic and the Symposium. The philosophical subject of the dialogue is the immortality of the soul. It is set in the last hours prior to the death of Socrates, and is Plato's fourth and last dialogue to detail the philosopher's final days, following Euthyphro, Apology, and Crito.

One of the main themes in the Phaedo is the idea that the soul is immortal. In the dialogue, Socrates discusses the nature of the afterlife on his last day before being executed by drinking hemlock. Socrates has been imprisoned and sentenced to death by an Athenian jury for not believing in the gods of the state (though some scholars think it was more for his support of "philosopher kings" as opposed to democracy)[2] and for corrupting the youth of the city.

By engaging in dialectic with a group of Socrates's friends, including the two Thebans, Cebes, and Simmias, Socrates explores various arguments for the soul's immortality in order to show that there is an afterlife in which the soul will dwell following death and, for couples and good people, be more at one with "every loving thing" and be more powerful than the Greek gods. Phaedo tells the story that following the discussion, he and the others were there to witness the death of Socrates.

The Phaedo was first translated into Latin from Greek by Apuleius but no copy survived, so Henry Aristippus produced a new translation in 1160.


Product Details

ISBN-13: 9781774419885
Publisher: Binker North
Publication date: 07/15/2023
Pages: 110
Product dimensions: 6.00(w) x 9.00(h) x 0.23(d)

About the Author

About The Author
Plato was an ancient Greek philosopher born in Athens during the Classical period in Ancient Greece. In Athens, Plato founded the Academy, a philosophical school where he taught the philosophical doctrines that would later become known as Platonism. Plato (or Platon) was a pen name derived, apparently, from the nickname given to him by his wrestling coach - allegedly a reference to his physical broadness. According to Alexander of Miletus quoted by Diogenes of Sinope his actual name was Aristocles, son of Ariston, of the deme Collytus (Collytus being a district of Athens).Plato was an innovator of the written dialogue and dialectic forms in philosophy. He raised problems for what later became all the major areas of both theoretical philosophy and practical philosophy. His most famous contribution is the Theory of forms, which has been interpreted as advancing a solution to what is now known as the problem of universals. He is also the namesake of Platonic love and the Platonic solids.His own most decisive philosophical influences are usually thought to have been, along with Socrates, the pre-Socratics Pythagoras, Heraclitus, and Parmenides, although few of his predecessors' works remain extant and much of what we know about these figures today derives from Plato himself.[a]Along with his teacher, Socrates, and his student, Aristotle, Plato is a central figure in the history of philosophy.[b] Unlike the work of nearly all of his contemporaries, Plato's entire body of work is believed to have survived intact for over 2,400 years.[6] Although their popularity has fluctuated, Plato's works have consistently been read and studied. Through Neoplatonism Plato also greatly influenced both Christian and Islamic philosophy (through e.g. Al-Farabi). In modern times, Alfred North Whitehead famously said: "the safest general characterization of the European philosophical tradition is that it consists of a series of footnotes to Plato.

Table of Contents

Prefaceix
List of Abbreviationsx
Introduction
IThe purpose of the dialogue and its position in the Platonic writings3
IIStylometric arguments. The transcendent forms8
IIIThe nature of the soul11
IVThe characters12
VThe arguments for the immortality of the soul16
VIArguments for immortality in other dialogues19
Translation and Commentary
I57A-59C: Introductory conversation27
II59C-62C: Socrates as poet. The wickedness of suicide32
III62C-64C: The philosopher's readiness to die39
IV64C-67B: The philosopher's detachment from the body44
V67B-69E: Moral virtue, genuine and spurious52
VI69E-72D: The first argument for immortality. The cycle of opposites58
VII72E-77A: A complementary argument. The theory of recollection66
VIII77A-78B: Combined results of the two preceding arguments. Socrates as charmer78
IX78B-80C: Third argument. The kinship of souls and forms81
X80C-82D: The after-life of unpurified souls87
XI82D-85B: Socrates describes the philosopher's progress and declares his swan-song to be a song of joy92
XII85B-88B: Simmias and Cebes explain their doubts97
XIII88C-91C: Interlude. A warning against 'misology'105
XIV91C-95A: Refutation of Simmias's theory of soul112
XV95A-99D: Socrates as student of natural science121
XVI99D-102A: The new method of hypothesis133
XVII102A-105B: The exclusion of opposites147
XVIII105B-107B: The argument concluded. Soul is both deathless and indestructible158
XIX107C-110B: Myth of the after-life167
XX110B-112E: The splendour of the true earth. The rivers of the underworld176
XXI112E-115A: The myth concluded. Its truth and value182
XXII115B-118: The last scene187
Additional Notes191
The Criticisms of Strato195
Index of Names199
From the B&N Reads Blog

Customer Reviews