Martin Buber's Theopolitics

Martin Buber's Theopolitics

by Samuel Hayim Brody
Martin Buber's Theopolitics

Martin Buber's Theopolitics

by Samuel Hayim Brody

eBook

$13.49  $17.99 Save 25% Current price is $13.49, Original price is $17.99. You Save 25%.

Available on Compatible NOOK devices, the free NOOK App and in My Digital Library.
WANT A NOOK?  Explore Now

Related collections and offers

LEND ME® See Details

Overview

How did one of the greatest Jewish thinkers of the 20th century grapple with the founding of Israel and the Israeli-Palestinian conflict—one of the most significant political conflicts of his time? Samuel Hayim Brody traces the development of Martin Buber's thinking and its implications for the Jewish religion, for the problems posed by Zionism, and for the Zionist-Arab conflict. Beginning in turbulent Weimar Germany, Brody shows how Buber's debates about Biblical meanings had concrete political consequences for anarchists, socialists, Zionists, Nazis, British, and Palestinians alike. Brody further reveals how Buber's passionate commitment to the rule of God absent an intermediary came into conflict in the face of a Zionist movement in danger of repeating ancient mistakes. Brody argues that Buber's support for Israel stemmed from a radically rich and complex understanding of the nature of the Jewish mission on earth that arose from an anarchist reading of the Bible.


Product Details

ISBN-13: 9780253035370
Publisher: Indiana University Press
Publication date: 02/16/2018
Series: New Jewish Philosophy and Thought
Sold by: Barnes & Noble
Format: eBook
Pages: 329
File size: 1 MB
Age Range: 18 Years

About the Author

Samuel Hayim Brody is Assistant Professor of Religious Studies at the University of Kansas. He is editor of Martin Buber Werkausgabe, volume 15.

Read an Excerpt

CHAPTER 1

The True Front

Buber and Landauer on Anarchism and Revolution

Me? I'm the king of the twentieth century. I'm the boogeyman. The villain ... The black sheep of the family.

— V to Evey, V for Vendetta

These anarchists are not anarchic enough for me.

— Gustav Landauer, "Anarchic Thoughts on Anarchism"

Introduction: Anarchism by Any Other Name

Martin Buber and Gustav Landauer met in Berlin circa 1900 at a gathering of the Neue Gemeinschaft (New Community), a mystical society that Landauer would shortly quit. The two men maintained a mutually beneficial intellectual and personal relationship for many years, often seeing each other nearly daily. They had a falling out during the Great War, when Landauer pilloried Buber's naïve exaltation of the supposedly noble spirit of sacrifice prevailing in Europe. This criticism led to an about-face in which Buber reexamined his previous philosophical commitments, beginning the process that would eventually lead to the publication of Ich und Du (I and Thou) in 1923. Before that happened, however, Landauer was murdered in May 1919 by the Freikorps (Free Corps) paramilitary troops sent from Berlin to put down the short-lived Bavarian Council Republic, and Buber honored his memory as the literary executor of his estate.

This narrative of friendship, told most definitively by Paul Mendes-Flohr, has been adopted by nearly every scholar since. Ordinarily, however, this story is invoked to say something about the origins of Buber's dialogic philosophy. Here, I attend more to the political implications of Buber's friendship with Landauer than to the gradual changes in his philosophical vocabulary, and I ask different questions: What does it mean that Buber spent nearly two decades as the close confidante of perhaps the most important German anarchist of the century? How should we understand the fact that, with the exception of Buber's interest in Palestine as a site for the realization of their shared ideals, and in the "Jewish movement" (of which Zionism was one part) as a potential vehicle for this realization, there is little to no daylight between the two men's political outlooks? This was especially true after 1916, when in the wake of Landauer's denunciation of Buber's war politics, Buber began to stress the dangers of nationalism and imperialism attendant on the Zionist effort.

It is not that Mendes-Flohr plays down these affinities. For example, he shows that Buber's 1918 essay Der Heilige Weg (The Holy Way) "indicates a considerable debt to Landauer, in particular to his political anarchism," and he notes that "the very first essays that mark this volte-face focus on the problem of the state." Nonetheless, later scholars have hesitated to fully develop these indications, and politics is underplayed in the secondary literature. Not only do scholars hesitate to describe Buber as an anarchist; some find it difficult to even admit that he has a politics at all. Maurice Friedman, for example, bases his claim that Buber was "neither a pacifist nor an anarchist like Gustav Landauer" on an exchange in August 1963 between Buber and a young student of the kibbutz movement, Hermann MeierCronemeyer. Having read Buber's work Paths in Utopia (1947), and his essay "Society and the State" (1951), Meier-Cronemeyer wrote to ask Buber why he did not refer to his politics of "the social principle" as "anarchism." Was it fear of the dubious reputation of the term? Buber responded that the term "anarchism" did not speak to him because "it means an overcoming of relations of power — which is impossible as long as the nature of man is what it is."

One could argue that this is ample evidence to justify Friedman's claim that Buber is not an anarchist, since he never explicitly avows anarchism, and on at least this one occasion he disavows it. One historian of anarchism, Peter Marshall, agrees: "Buber ultimately parted company with the anarchists by arguing that the State can in some circumstances have a legitimate role." However, as another historian of anarchism, George Woodcock, has shown, there has been an increasing tendency over the years for anarchists to embrace the view "that human beings are improvable but not ... perfectible. We must accept the probability of imperfection and limit anti-sociality where it impinges on the lives of others. ... The more we build and strengthen an alternative society, the more the state is weakened." By these lights, the precise view in the name of which Buber disavowed anarchism is declared to be anarchism. Acceptance of this wider understanding of anarchism, developed partially under the influence of renewed readings of Landauer himself, explains why other scholars since the 1970s have felt little need to justify calling Buber an anarchist. In uncritically accepting Buber's distinction between his own politics and anarchism, however, Friedman continuously describes Buber's political orientation using awkward euphemisms and neologisms, such as "the politics of the social principle."

Yet Buber himself set the precedent for these vague, cumbersome labels. He knew well, for example, that Landauer understood his own anarchism not to en tail any kind of final, idyllic "overcoming of power-relations." On the contrary, Landauer argued in a work commissioned and published by Buber himself that "no revolution will ever achieve its goals." In his 1947 work Paths in Utopia, Buber praises Landauer for declining to formulate "the absolute goal," for understanding that "all true socialism is relative," and for his insight that "socialism is not the invention of anything new but the discovery of something actually present, of something that has grown." As Buber explains, Paths in Utopia is structured progressively, unfolding a core idea from its beginnings: "In the history of utopian socialism three pairs of active thinkers emerge, each pair being bound together in a peculiar way and also to its generation: Saint-Simon and Fourier, Owen and Proudhon, Kropotkin and Gustav Landauer." Buber here places Landauer at the end of an intellectual lineage that includes the classical anarchist theorists Pierre-Joseph Proudhon (1809–1865) and Peter Kropotkin (1842–1921), arguing that he makes essential improvements on this line of thought, from within it. He also, however, designates this line of thought as "socialism" or "utopian socialism." Buber is aware that "socialism" is a term that, like "democracy," allows for variants, and the purpose of Paths in Utopia is to discern a particular line within that term. Despite the fact, however, that those whom he treats in the book's central chapters all referred to themselves as anarchists, and used "anarchism" and "socialism" interchangeably (from Proudhon on this is a defining trait of "utopian socialism" as against its "scientific" cousin, Marxism), he declines to use this term himself but alternates between assorted alternatives. This sets the precedent for all the vagaries in the secondary literature, which reference Buber's "social philosophy" rather than his political thought, or his "decentralized federalism" or espousal of "anocracy" rather than his relationship to anarchism. Meier-Cronemeyer may have been right to suggest that Buber was afraid to be tarred with the anarchist brush, hoping to have more success with utopian socialism.

If, however, there is little to no difference between Buber and Landauer on the plane of political and social theory, then this deserves greater recognition. In the end, such recognition might lead one to remove Landauer from the list of anarchist authors rather than add Buber to it. Yet for scholars to argue that Buber has no politics, or to take him at his word in distinguishing his politics from anarchism, without investigating his relationship to Landauer and other anarchist thinkers, is to take sides unwittingly in a dispute among socialists. Moreover, there is a sense in which terminology is destiny. There is an anarchist "canon," in which William Godwin (1756–1836), Proudhon, Mikhail Bakunin (1814–1876), and Kropotkin, along with Alexander Berkman (1870–1936), Rudolf Rocker (1873–1958), and Emma Goldman (1869–1940), number among the classics. For the most part, this canon receives little academic attention as compared to its Marxist "big brother," and it is studied today primarily by those personally attracted to anarchism. Buber demonstrates in Paths in Utopia that he knows this literature well, often thanks to Landauer's translations, but Buber scholars have shown little interest in contextualizing their understanding of Buber through independent exploration of anarchist thought. Consequently, the general perception of his politics follows the nebulous lines that Friedman, following Buber himself, laid down.

Landauer before Buber: Anarchist Activism, 1890–1899

When he met Buber, Landauer already had a long record of radical agitation behind him. In fact, at that very moment he was embroiled in a highly politicized libel case, which would result in a six-month prison sentence. Moritz von Egidy, a former lieutenant colonel who became a Christian anarchist and pacifist, had asked Landauer's help in securing a retrial for Albert Ziethen, a prisoner whom von Egidy believed to have been railroaded. In February 1898, Landauer published an article in his newspaper, Der Sozialist, accusing a Berlin police official of manufacturing evidence in the case, and he repeated the charges in a letter to members of the Reichstag and the state's attorney's office. But von Egidy died before the trial, and Landauer dedicated the entire January 1899 issue of Der Sozialist to his memory. In that issue Landauer quotes this passage by von Egidy, which he could have easily written himself: "Unthinking men connect the idea of 'Anarchy' with the idea of disorder; that, however, is contained neither in the word nor in the strivings of those who call themselves anarchists. On the contrary: a more complete order, an order that rests upon self-discipline and self-rule; an order without force." A month later, still in mourning for his friend, Landauer attended the meeting of the Neue Gemeinschaft at which he met his second wife, Hedwig Lachmann, and other future collaborators, possibly including Buber.

Commenting on the early years of Buber and Landauer's friendship, Mendes-Flohr contends that "Buber's earlier intellectual relationship with Landauer was found[ed] on common aesthetic and metaphysical concerns; political and social questions were almost entirely absent from their prewar relationship." I would qualify this judgment in two ways: first, at the moment that Landauer and Buber first met, the former was on the cusp of a withdrawal from his stormy public political career, which would persist for the first eight years of their acquaintance. Second, I emphasize different elements of Buber's 1904 essay on Landauer's thought. These steps will help us determine the extent to which Buber and Landauer agreed politically before the outbreak of the Great War, in order to contextualize their subsequent relationship. However, we have to consider Landauer's life and career before his encounter with Buber, in order to avoid defining their initial interest in each other according to their later accomplishments.

Landauer was born in Karlsruhe in 1870, nearly twins with Otto von Bismarck's united Germany. In 1875, the Sozialistische Arbeiterpartei Deutschlands (SAPD) was established through the fusion of the two previously dominant leftwing factions: Ferdinand Lassalle's Allgemeiner Deutscher Arbeiterverein (General German Workers' Association) and the Sozialdemokratische Arbeiterpartei Deutschlands (Social Democratic Workers' Party of Germany) of Wilhelm Liebknecht and August Bebel. The Sozialistengesetze (Socialist Laws) of 1878 attempted to outlaw socialist organizing but failed, and when Bismarck retired in 1890, the Reichstag declined to renew them. Now allowed to organize openly once again, the SAPD renamed itself the Sozialdemokratische Partei Deutschlands (SPD), the Social Democratic Party of Germany. Between 1891 and 1914, the SPD expanded continually until it became the single largest party in the country.

The lapse of the antisocialist laws occurred when Landauer was twenty years old, a student of German classicism and romanticism at University of Berlin. At that point, however, he was more interested in his studies than in new opportunities for activism, and he soon left Berlin for a term at University of Strasbourg (1890–1891), during which he read Nietzsche's Birth of Tragedy and Thus Spoke Zarathustra. He was profoundly influenced by Nietzsche's passionate advocacy of free, individual creativity, and he would eventually strive to integrate his politics with Nietzsche's philosophy, despite the latter's virulent antipathy to socialism and anarchism. Upon his return to Berlin in April 1891, Landauer became involved with the Freie Volksbühne (Free People's Theater), an institution established by the socialist Bruno Wille for the cultural education of the working class through cheap access to theatrical performances. It was through Wille and his theater that Landauer met the group that would introduce him to anarchism.

Funding for the Freie Volksbühne was provided by the SPD, which had grown from a mere political party into a mass cultural institution. However, the SPD's growth was not without its casualties. At a party convention in Erfurt in 1891, the newly legalized SPD adopted the program of Karl Kautsky, both recommitting itself to the seizure of the means of production from capitalists and endorsing the moderate and legally available means of parliamentary activity. Kautsky reasoned that revolution was inevitable according to the Marxist understanding of history, such that the socialist task was the amelioration of workers' living conditions until the final battle in the class struggle. In the course of the debate over the Erfurt Program, a group of radical youth who had been members of the SAPD and who advocated boycotting electoral politics were expelled from the congress, and as a result they excluded themselves from the newly formed SPD. Known as the Verein der unabhängigen Sozialisten (Association of Independent Socialists), or simply the Jungen (Young Ones), this was the group with whom Landauer chose to affiliate upon his entrance into political activism. As a result, he could later say, "I was an anarchist before I was a socialist, and one of the few who had not taken a detour via social democracy." For Landauer, the conflict with the Jungen marked the SPD as rotten from the beginning, and in 1919, only weeks before he would die at the hands of its contracted militiamen, he declared, "In the entire natural history I know of no more disgusting creature than the Social Democratic Party."

The split of the Jungen led rapidly to the founding of two projects that heavily involved Landauer. The first was the newspaper Der Sozialist, the official organ of the dissenters; Landauer soon became one of its primary editors. In its opening statement of purpose, the newspaper charged the SPD executive with opportunism, reformism, and authoritarianism: "We are opponents of legislative-parliamentary activity; experience has shown that it leads unavoidably to corruption and possibilism. We must stress the fact that parliament is an institution through which the bourgeoisie exercises its rule over the proletariat." Landauer's early articles focused on the antistatist socialism of figures like Eugen Dühring (1833–1921) and Benedikt Friedländer (1866–1908), a friend and neighbor who introduced Landauer to the work of Max Stirner. The title Der Sozialist was retained as a polemical thrust that anarchism was the only true socialism; in 1895 Landauer changed the subtitle of the paper to Organ für Anarchismus-Sozialismus, arguing that "anyone who is not blinded by the dogmas of the political parties will recognize that anarchism and socialism are not opposed but co-dependent. True cooperative labor and true community can only exist where individuals are free, and free individuals can only exist where our needs are met by brotherly solidarity." In the fall of 1892 the second project was born when Wille and others accused the SPD of attempting to turn the Freie Volksbühne into an arm of the party, forming the Neue Freie Volksbühne in response. Landauer served on the board of the new theater for several years.

(Continues…)



Excerpted from "Martin Buber's Theopolitics"
by .
Copyright © 2018 samuel hayim Brody.
Excerpted by permission of Indiana University Press.
All rights reserved. No part of this excerpt may be reproduced or reprinted without permission in writing from the publisher.
Excerpts are provided by Dial-A-Book Inc. solely for the personal use of visitors to this web site.

Table of Contents

Preface
Acknowledgments
Note on Translation/Transliteration
List of Abbreviations
Introduction: What is Theopolitics?
Part One: From Anarchism to Anarcho-Theocracy: The Birth of Theopolitics
1. The True Front: Buber and Landauer on Anarchism and Revolution
2. The Serpent: Theopolitics from Weimar to Nazi Germany
3. God against Messiah: The Kingship of God and the Ancient Israelite Anarcho-Theocracy
Part Two: The Anointed and the Prophet: Theopolitics in Israel from Exodus to Exile
4. Between Pharaohs and Nomads: Moses
5. The Arcanum of the Monarchy: The Anointed
6. The Battle for YHVH: The Prophetic Faith
Part Three: Theopolitics and Zion
7. Palestinian Rain: Zionism as Applied Theopolitics
8. This Pathless Hour: Theopolitics in the Present
Conclusion: The Narrow Ridge, the Razor's Edge
Appendix: Martin Buber to Hans Kohn, 10/4/1939
Bibliography
Index

What People are Saying About This

Michael L. Morgan

What Samuel Hayim Brody has done is to focus on Martin Buber as a political thinker and to consider the character of his fundamental political ideas and commitments. He does this primarily as an intellectual historian, with a very rich sense of Buber's political activities and involvements. Brilliantly conceived, well-written, filled with deep readings and analysis.

Asher Biemann

Samuel Hayim Brody's book addresses an absolutely central, yet hitherto neglected, topic in Martin Buber's thought, which not only situates his philosophical trajectory in an intellectual-historical context, especially of the Weimar years, but also makes a persuasive argument for the pivotal role of theopolitics in that trajectory. A majesterial study in every way and certain to become the authoritative book in its field.

From the B&N Reads Blog

Customer Reviews