Kinaesthetic Knowing: Aesthetics, Epistemology, Modern Design
Is all knowledge the product of thought? Or can the physical interactions of the body with the world produce reliable knowledge? In late-nineteenth-century Europe, scientists, artists, and other intellectuals theorized the latter as a new way of knowing, which Zeynep Çelik Alexander here dubs “kinaesthetic knowing.”     
In this book, Alexander offers the first major intellectual history of kinaesthetic knowing and its influence on the formation of modern art and architecture and especially modern design education. Focusing in particular on Germany and tracing the story up to the start of World War II, Alexander reveals the tension between intellectual meditation and immediate experience to be at the heart of the modern discourse of aesthetics, playing a major part in the artistic and teaching practices of numerous key figures of the period, including Heinrich Wölfflin, Hermann Obrist, August Endell, László Moholy-Nagy, and many others. Ultimately, she shows, kinaesthetic knowing did not become the foundation of the human sciences, as some of its advocates had hoped, but it did lay the groundwork—at such institutions as the Bauhaus—for modern art and architecture in the twentieth century. 
 
1125945920
Kinaesthetic Knowing: Aesthetics, Epistemology, Modern Design
Is all knowledge the product of thought? Or can the physical interactions of the body with the world produce reliable knowledge? In late-nineteenth-century Europe, scientists, artists, and other intellectuals theorized the latter as a new way of knowing, which Zeynep Çelik Alexander here dubs “kinaesthetic knowing.”     
In this book, Alexander offers the first major intellectual history of kinaesthetic knowing and its influence on the formation of modern art and architecture and especially modern design education. Focusing in particular on Germany and tracing the story up to the start of World War II, Alexander reveals the tension between intellectual meditation and immediate experience to be at the heart of the modern discourse of aesthetics, playing a major part in the artistic and teaching practices of numerous key figures of the period, including Heinrich Wölfflin, Hermann Obrist, August Endell, László Moholy-Nagy, and many others. Ultimately, she shows, kinaesthetic knowing did not become the foundation of the human sciences, as some of its advocates had hoped, but it did lay the groundwork—at such institutions as the Bauhaus—for modern art and architecture in the twentieth century. 
 
59.0 In Stock
Kinaesthetic Knowing: Aesthetics, Epistemology, Modern Design

Kinaesthetic Knowing: Aesthetics, Epistemology, Modern Design

by Zeynep Çelik Alexander
Kinaesthetic Knowing: Aesthetics, Epistemology, Modern Design

Kinaesthetic Knowing: Aesthetics, Epistemology, Modern Design

by Zeynep Çelik Alexander

Hardcover

$59.00 
  • SHIP THIS ITEM
    Qualifies for Free Shipping
  • PICK UP IN STORE

    Your local store may have stock of this item.

Related collections and offers


Overview

Is all knowledge the product of thought? Or can the physical interactions of the body with the world produce reliable knowledge? In late-nineteenth-century Europe, scientists, artists, and other intellectuals theorized the latter as a new way of knowing, which Zeynep Çelik Alexander here dubs “kinaesthetic knowing.”     
In this book, Alexander offers the first major intellectual history of kinaesthetic knowing and its influence on the formation of modern art and architecture and especially modern design education. Focusing in particular on Germany and tracing the story up to the start of World War II, Alexander reveals the tension between intellectual meditation and immediate experience to be at the heart of the modern discourse of aesthetics, playing a major part in the artistic and teaching practices of numerous key figures of the period, including Heinrich Wölfflin, Hermann Obrist, August Endell, László Moholy-Nagy, and many others. Ultimately, she shows, kinaesthetic knowing did not become the foundation of the human sciences, as some of its advocates had hoped, but it did lay the groundwork—at such institutions as the Bauhaus—for modern art and architecture in the twentieth century. 
 

Product Details

ISBN-13: 9780226485201
Publisher: University of Chicago Press
Publication date: 12/08/2017
Pages: 336
Product dimensions: 7.00(w) x 10.00(h) x 1.10(d)

About the Author

Zeynep Çelik Alexander is an architectural historian. She is associate professor at the Department of Art History and Archaeology, Columbia University.

Read an Excerpt

CHAPTER 1

Kinaesthetic Knowing

The Nineteenth-Century Biography of Another Kind of Knowledge

In the spring of 1853, a thirty-two-year-old Hermann von Helmholtz, professor of physiology at the University of Königsberg, stood before the German Society in the same city to deliver a lecture in which he attempted to answer a troubling question. How was it possible, Helmholtz wondered, that Goethe, the "comprehensive genius" and the embodiment of the German ideal of culture, had been so blatantly wrong in his scientific studies of color and light? Helmholtz was referring to the 1810 treatise Zur Farbenlehre (Theory of Color), a text in which Goethe had wielded his extensive description of the phenomenal and experiential aspects of light as a weapon against the mechanistic logic of Newtonian physics. Goethe's insistence on refuting the Newtonian principles upon which scientific practice had been so successfully predicated seemed irreconcilable with his genius. Helmholtz thus speculated:

On the one side are a number of physicists, who, by a long series of the ablest investigations, the most elaborate calculations, and the most ingenious inventions, have brought optics to such perfection, that it, and it alone, among the physical sciences, was beginning almost to rival astronomy in accuracy. ... On the other side is a man whose remarkable mental endowments, and whose singular talent for seeing through whatever obscures reality, we have had occasion to recognize, not only in poetry, but also in the descriptive parts of the natural sciences; and this man assures us with the utmost zeal that the physicists are wrong: he is so convinced of the correctness of his own view, that he cannot explain the contradiction except by assuming narrowness or malice on their part. ... So flat a contradiction leads us to suspect that there must be behind some deeper antagonism of principle, some difference of organization between his mind and theirs, to prevent them from understanding each other.

According to Helmholtz, Goethe's ingenuity had been to recognize forms in the formless heap of phenomena and to induce types from them. Goethe regarded nature first and foremost as a work of art, complete in itself: not under concepts independent of intuition (anschauungslose Begriffe) but rather in forms "inspired by a direct spiritual intuition" (unmittelbare geistige Anschauung). Goethe was at his best when he recognized that the human skull carried formal traces of the intermaxillary bone found in other vertebrates, when he observed that the stem, leaves, petals, and stamens of a palm plant formally resembled each other, or when he described the afterimages of shapes and colors. Under Goethe's gaze, nature was no longer a collection of haphazard fragments but became comprehensible as an organic whole. It was no coincidence, Helmholtz noted, that Goethe had realized his most brilliant scientific work in such "descriptive" sciences as botany, zoology, or anatomy. When phenomena needed to be portrayed, compared, or classified according to their form or structure, Goethe proved to be a genius. However, when phenomena needed to be analyzed and their causes explained, Helmholtz noted, Goethe's morphological thinking did not fare as well (fig. 1.1).

Yet Helmholtz was not prepared to call Goethe's scientific endeavors a failure, either. He detected in the poet's intuitive approach to nature an intense antipathy to dissection (Zergliederung) and a resolute resistance to understanding phenomena in any manner that was not aesthetic. In Goethe's thinking, "nature resists the interference of the experimenter who tortures and disturbs her," he wrote. Helmholtz was also aware that his own work in physics and physiology penetrated precisely that which Goethe had deemed impenetrable: the deep mechanical laws at work in "the levers, the cords, and the pulleys which work behind the scenes" as opposed to "the beautiful appearance of nature." Thus, instead of calling a winner and a loser in what was in fact Goethe's long-lost war against Newton, Helmholtz tactfully proposed an alternative. The reasoning practiced by Newton and Goethe, he offered, should be understood as guided by competing epistemic principles. Newton's reasoning followed logical induction, which, with the aid of syllogisms, "reduced a question to clearly defined universal propositions." Goethe, by contrast, subscribed to another kind of reasoning that Helmholtz described as aesthetic or artistic induction (künstlerische Induction). Aesthetic induction also followed the protocols of syllogistic reasoning but was performed by the body as opposed to by the mind. For example, the eye drew conclusions from major premises (what one had in store as past experience) and minor premises (sensations locally presented to it in the current moment) in perception as if there were a logician embedded in it. Unlike a logical induction, however, an aesthetic induction was carried out unconsciously. Helmholtz called these "judgments which do not depend upon our consciously thinking over former observations of the same kind ... 'unconscious inferences' [unbewußte Schlüsse]." Each kind of induction corresponded to a distinct mode of ratiocination:

Besides the knowledge [Wissen] that operates with concepts [Begriffe] and is, therefore, capable of expression in words, there is another department of our mental operations, which only combines sensual impressions [sinnliche Eindrücke] that are not capable of direct verbal expression. In German we call this Kennen — as when we say that we "know" a man, a road, a dish, an odorous substance, we mean that we have seen, or tasted, or smelt these objects, hold on to their sensual impression in memory, and will recognize it again when it is repeated, even though we may never be able to describe the impression in words, even to ourselves.

Viewed from the perspective of the Helmholtzian distinction between Wissen and Kennen, the difference between Goethe and Newton no longer seemed irreconcilable. Even when they concerned themselves with the same object, Helmholtz explained, the two pursued different kinds of knowledge. In Zur Farbenlehre Goethe poetically described the experiential effects of light: he was interested in how the sensorial apparatus of his body experienced itself, perceived afterimages and illusions, and associated phenomenal effects with moral values (fig. 1.2). By contrast, Newton, even when he gathered evidence from observation or experiment, was concerned with formulating principles of causality beyond such experiential effects. As others who ruminated on the same epistemological distinction would put it, while Goethe wanted to know light, Newton wanted to know about light. Kennen, then, was acquired through an experiential familiarity with phenomena; Wissen attempted to establish supra- experiential facts by inquiring into questions of cause and effect. Kennen required the description of appearances and analogical reasoning; Wissen, the analysis of the machinery behind appearances and causal reasoning.

In fact, Helmholtz's distinction sought to reconcile more than the long-standing antagonism between Goethe and Newton. In a theoretical move that would prove anticipatory of the organization of the disciplines at universities at the end of the century, Helmholtz associated Wissen and Kennen with distinct fields of knowledge whose differences would now have to be understood in methodological terms. Logical induction belonged with the natural sciences (Naturwissenschaften), whose contributions to Prussia's modernization were widely recognized and celebrated by the middle of the nineteenth century despite ongoing debates about their role in education. By contrast, Helmholtz argued, aesthetic induction was at home with the arts and the loosely defined human sciences (Geisteswissenschaften; what we call the humanities and the social sciences in North America today), sciences of the mind whose intellectual rigor was considered central to the nineteenth-century ideal of Bildung.

Helmholtz's theoretical move was as deft as it was reconciliatory. Whereas positivism argued that all fields of knowledge be reformed on the methodological model of the natural sciences and the German Historical School insisted on the separation of the natural sciences from the human sciences, Helmholtz diverted the debate by attributing the difference between these two constellations of fields to two distinct kinds of knowing. Still questions remained: however similar the basic operation of aesthetic induction and that of logical induction might be, could one assume that the two kinds of knowledge were equally legitimate? To what extent was each reliable in guiding action? Helmholtz himself expressed some reservations. Aesthetic induction could "never be perfectly assimilated to forms of logical reasoning," he wrote, "nor pressed so far to establish universal laws." Still, given the central role that it played in the translation of sensations into perception, he thought that Kennen held the promise of another kind of rigor:

And yet it is certain that this kind of knowledge [Kennen] may attain the highest possible degree of precision and certainty, and is so far not inferior to any knowledge [Wissen] which can be expressed in words; but it is not directly communicable, unless the object in qestion can be brought actually forward, or the impression that it produces can be otherwise represented — as by drawing the portrait of a man instead of producing the man himself. ... I would also note here that this "knowledge" of the effort of the will [Willensimpuls] to be exerted must attain the highest possible degree of certainty, accuracy, and precision, for us to be able to maintain so artificial a balance as is necessary for walking on stilts or for skating, for the singer to know how to strike a note with his voice, or the violin-player with his finger, so exactly that its vibration shall not be out by a hundredth part.

This chapter is the intellectual biography of the kind of knowing that Helmholtz dubbed Kennen, the kind of knowledge, which, despite its resistance to language, concepts, propositions, or representations, was nonetheless understood to guide correctly the fingers of a violinist, the voice of an opera singer, or the hand of an artist. This history is crucial to understanding the emergence of the late-nineteenth and early-twentieth-century techniques that I discuss in subsequent chapters. As I explained in the introductory chapter, I call this other way of knowing "kinaesthetic knowing": nondiscursive and nonconceptual knowledge assumed to be gathered from the body's experiential exchanges with the world. This is not to say that kinaesthetic knowing had no discursive existence before Helmholtz theorized it in the middle of the nineteenth century. I will briefly summarize in the next section how others before and after Helmholtz proposed the idea that there might exist a unique form of ratiocination associated with the musculature of the body. Yet it was at the middle of the nineteenth century, in the midst of heated debates about teleology and mechanism, that kinaesthetic knowing acquired unprecedented salience. The dependence of this alternative mode of knowing upon experience, as we will see, allowed it to accommodate teleological and mechanistic explanations simultaneously. The political expediency of this accommodation proved crucial to the success of kinaesthetic knowing: for such debates did not only purport to explain the order of the universe theoretically but also sought to dictate the order of the world here and now.

The Longer Historical Arc: From Sympathy to Proprioception

Kennen differed from other theorizations of experiential knowledge — intuitive, instinctive, or otherwise — in that Helmholtz assumed that it was attained by the musculature of the body. In his monumental study on the physiology of vision, he stressed — over against the usual arguments for the perfection of the eye as evidence of God and preexisting harmony in the universe — that the eye had numerous inherent flaws: chromatic irregularity, spherical aberration, and imperfect transparency, among many others. If, despite these flaws, it was still able to provide the subject with a correct perception of the world, it was because and only because of the tireless work undertaken by the eye muscles. By constantly adjusting and readjusting themselves, these muscles overcame potential misperceptions and illusions and eventually learned to draw the correct inference from the sensations presented to the eye (figs. 1.3, 1.4). It was almost as if muscles toiled away with a work ethic that Weber would later associate with Protestantism.

In this sense, the history of Kennen was intertwined with that of the concept of the reflex, which from the seventeenth century onward offered a new way of accounting for the coordinated action of the muscles. Galenic theories that dominated Europe before the rise of reflex theory had imagined the human body as demonstrating a decentralized sentience: parts of the body responded in "sympathy" or "consensus" with other parts through a network of fibers and vessels (fig. 1.5). By contrast, reflex theory assumed that a centrally located sensus communis "reflected" the animal spirits activated by external impressions, which, in turn, triggered muscle movement. The mechanism of reflex action was famously noted by the philosopher René Descartes and examined by the physician Thomas Willis, but by the beginning of the nineteenth century, the work of a number of physicians established the concept in the modern sense as the involuntary response of the body to external stimuli. The reflex, however, raised as many questions about the configuration of the human subject as it answered. How was the relationship between the centers of the body and its peripheries to be theorized in light of reflex theory? What was the connection between voluntary and involuntary actions? How was the theological concept of the soul to be negotiated with an emergent concept of the mind? Furthermore, as Margarete Vöhringer has demonstrated, such questions acquired political resonances after the French Revolution, when the spectacle of the king's beheading by guillotine also turned out to be a physiological experiment performed in public about the reflex.

The discourse around muscle action assumed new salience after the Scottish surgeon Charles Bell and the French physiologist François Magendie independently discovered in the mid-1820s that nerves carrying sensory impulses and those carrying motor impulses were attached to different parts of the spinal cord. These findings suggested that if muscles were capable of transmitting afferent impulses toward the central nervous system as well as efferent ones away from it, they might have a sentience comparable to that of the eye or the ear. Using physiological evidence, especially of the human hand, Bell argued that the "exercise of the muscular frame [was] the source of much of the knowledge which [was] usually supposed to be obtained through the organs of sense." Bell called this consciousness the "sixth sense" or the "muscle sense" — by which he meant the ability to sense tactility as well as the resistance of matter (fig. 1.6). In the early nineteenth century other natural philosophers also found epistemological value in the activities of the "muscle sense," alternatively referred to as Muskelsinn, Muskelgefühl, Innervationsgefühl, or sens musculaire. Especially within British and American philosophical traditions, the kind of knowledge that Helmholtz called Kennen was pitted against discursive knowledge under various rubrics and granted various degrees of autonomy: John Grote's and William James's "knowledge of acquaintance" versus "knowledge-about" or "knowledge of judgment"; Bertrand Russell's "knowledge by acquaintance" versus "knowledge by description"; or Gilbert Ryle's "knowledge-how" versus "knowledge-what." The conclusions drawn from the new sense, however, were contradictory. On the one hand, the muscle sense finalized the demise of the theory of "sympathies" by proving once and for all that every nervous impulse had to pass through the center, whether the brain or the spinal cord. On the other hand, the separation of the nerve traffic meant that muscles, equipped with sensory and motor nerves and responsible for the organism's mobility, could now be understood as self-governing entities on the peripheries of the body. It was in this immediate context that Helmholtz associated Kennen with psychologisches Tactgefühl, a psychological tactfulness that retained its ties with the sense of touch.

(Continues…)



Excerpted from "Kinaesthetic Knowing"
by .
Copyright © 2017 The University of Chicago.
Excerpted by permission of The University of Chicago Press.
All rights reserved. No part of this excerpt may be reproduced or reprinted without permission in writing from the publisher.
Excerpts are provided by Dial-A-Book Inc. solely for the personal use of visitors to this web site.

Table of Contents

Introduction: A Peculiar Experiment

1          Kinaesthetic Knowing: The Nineteenth-Century Biography of Another Kind of Knowledge
2          Looking: Wölfflin’s Comparative Vision
3          Affecting: Endell’s Mathematics of Living Feeling
4          Drawing: The Debschitz School and Formalism’s Subject
5          Designing: Discipline and Introspection at the Bauhaus

Epilogue


Acknowledgments
Notes
Selected Bibliography
Index
From the B&N Reads Blog

Customer Reviews