Just Food: Philosophy, Justice and Food

Just Food: Philosophy, Justice and Food

Just Food: Philosophy, Justice and Food

Just Food: Philosophy, Justice and Food

eBook

$50.00 

Available on Compatible NOOK Devices and the free NOOK Apps.
WANT A NOOK?  Explore Now

Related collections and offers

LEND ME® See Details

Overview

Who has access, and who is denied access, to food, and why? What are the consequences of food insecurity? What would it take for the food system to be just?

Just Food: Philosophy, Justice and Food presents thirteen new philosophical essays that explore the causes and consequences of the inequities of our contemporary food system. It examines why 842 million people globally are unable to meet their dietary needs, and why food insecurity is not simply a matter of insufficient supply. The book looks at how food insecurity tracks other social injustices, covering topics such as race, gender and property, as well as food sovereignty, food deserts, and locavorism. The essays in this volume make an important and timely contribution to the wider philosophical debate around food distribution and justice.




Product Details

ISBN-13: 9781783483884
Publisher: Rowman & Littlefield Publishers, Inc.
Publication date: 11/09/2015
Sold by: Barnes & Noble
Format: eBook
Pages: 240
File size: 787 KB
Age Range: 18 Years

About the Author

J.M. Dieterle is Professor of Philosophy at Eastern Michigan University. She has published articles in Public Affairs Quarterly, Bioethics, Environmental Ethics, Philosophia Mathematica and Erkenntnis.

Margaret Crouch, Professor of Philosophy, Eastern Michigan University; J.M. Dieterle, Professor of Philosophy, Eastern Michigan University; Liz Goodnick, Assistant Professor of Philosophy, Metropolitan State University of Denver; Stephen Minister, Associate Professor of Philosophy, Augustana College; Mark Navin, Associate Professor of Philosophy, Oakland University;; J. Michael Scoville, Assistant Professor of Philosophy, Eastern Michigan University; Nancy E. Snow, Professor and Director of the Institute for the Study of Human Flourishing, University of Oklahoma; Jennifer Szende, Postdoctoral Fellow, Centre de Recherche en Éthique de l’Université de Montreal; Steve Tammalleo, Assistant Professor of Philosophy, University of San Diego; Paul B. Thompson, WK Kellogg Chair in Agricultural, Food and Community Ethics, Michigan State University; Shakara Tyler, Graduate Student, Michigan State University; Lori Watson, Associate Professor of Philosophy, University of San Diego; Nancy Williams, Associate Professor of Philosophy, Wofford College; Ian Werkheiser, Assistant Professor, University of Texas Rio Grande Valley.



Read an Excerpt

Just Food

Philosophy, Justice and Food


By J. M. Dieterle

Rowman & Littlefield International Ltd.

Copyright © 2015 J. M. Dieterle
All rights reserved.
ISBN: 978-1-78348-388-4



CHAPTER 1

Framing Food Justice

J. Michael Scoville


The discussion of food justice norms tends to be focused on three main concerns. One is distributive issues, for example, whether all people have access to safe and healthy food, or whether everyone working within the food system is paid fairly and able to work in a safe environment. A second concern is issues of representation and political voice. Here the focus is whether all people are capable of participating in relevant decision making and the construction of public policies relating to the production, consumption and distribution of food. A third concern is the normatively significant connections between, on the one hand, the values of food and food-related practices, and on the other, collective self-determination. This third focus is often expressed in terms of food sovereignty, and has its origin in peasant social movements, notably, La Via Campesina. Discussion of these three concerns is complex, subject to ongoing disagreement and practically fraught.

Different views of what justice requires always reflect particular framings of what questions or concerns are thought to be crucial. Not surprisingly, the question of which framing (or framings) is best is controversial. With this in mind, I assume it is critically important to consider sustainability as a relevant framing for any contemporary theorizing about justice. Articulating an account of food justice, specifically, in isolation from broader questions about sustainability would leave many important normative issues unaddressed. The primary aim of this chapter is to explore how our thinking about food justice norms might be guided, constrained and in general enriched if we consider these norms in relation to sustainability.

A difficulty for this proposed focus is that many philosophers (among others) have viewed the concept of sustainability with suspicion. Reasons for this range from concern about sustainability being hopelessly vague and hence useless for policy, to concern that interest in sustainability is just the latest cover for business as usual and thus a betrayal of the environmental cause. While I believe such concerns are unconvincing, there is no question that sustainability is a contested concept — one that needs careful specification and defense if it is to do any work helping to frame discussions of food justice.

I assume that a significant reason to care about sustainability is the worry that we are shortchanging future generations through our collective conduct, giving them less than is their due. This is partly a matter of justice, but it is also a broader question of what we ought to be doing to preserve conditions that will make life worth living in the future. With this in mind, a fundamental aim of discussions of sustainability should be to clarify the X that we ought to be preserving, insofar as we can, for future generations both as a matter of justice and as a condition for living worthwhile lives. The challenge is to clarify the relevant X and the normative account that supports it.

In my reading of the literature, there are basically three types of sustainability views. One, which I'll call "the minimalist view," aims to specify our obligations to present and future generations (of human beings) in terms of maintaining the capacity to be well off. A second, which I'll refer to as "the human flourishing account," rests on the belief that human beings need access to a variety of specific and disaggregated goods, experiences and relationships in order to achieve well-being. A third incorporates aspects of the first two, but includes in addition nonanthropocentric reasons; I'll call this "the demanding view." Depending on the view of sustainability one adopts, there can be significantly different implications for how we should think about, and try to realize in practice, food justice. I explore some of these implications with respect to each type of sustainability view sketched.


I. THE MINIMALIST VIEW

A number of economists and philosophers defend something like what I'm calling the minimalist view. Despite differences in detail, defenders of this view more or less share three basic commitments. First, the core ethical commitment of the minimalist view is that the obligation of sustainability requires the present generation to aim at enabling all people, present and future, to have the option or capacity to be well off. With respect to the X that we ought to be sustaining, defenders of the minimalist view answer that our collective aim should be to maintain a nondeclining stock of total capital assets, which is assumed to be necessary for maintaining welfare over time. This stock is understood broadly and includes a diversity of things — for example, infrastructure, knowledge, technology and savings and investment, as well as the various resources and life-support functions provided by nature (commonly referred to as "natural capital"). Of course, there could be a nondeclining stock of the relevant goods and yet people might lack access to it. So defenders of the minimalist view should be read as assuming that all people should have access to the relevant goods as a matter of basic justice.

A second commitment of the minimalist view concerns the conception of welfare or well-being that is presupposed. Some prominent defenders of this view assume a desire or preference satisfaction account, where welfare consists in the satisfaction of an individual's desires or preferences. Such a view faces serious difficulties. Desires and preferences are highly adaptable, largely dependent on what is, or is expected to be, available, and can be distorted in ways that give us no reason to aim at satisfying them. Further, the fact that desires and preferences are subject to great variation, dependent as they are on changing circumstances, presents a problem when we try to clarify the content of our obligations to future generations. After all, how can we know with any certainty what future people will desire or prefer? If we endorse a modest "ought implies can" principle, then a desire or preference satisfaction account has the result of potentially undermining, or at least leaving largely unspecifiable, our obligations to future people. This implication may be unintended, but that hardly removes the problem.

To avoid these difficulties, the minimalist view does best to incorporate a need-based conception of well-being. Though the specification of the relevant needs is theory dependent, and not without controversy, it seems reasonable to think that theorists and policy makers could clarify a set of "core" or basic needs that would focus and guide social and political decision making. A statement from James Sterba suggests the general idea here: "Basic needs, if not satisfied, lead to significant lacks and deficiencies with respect to a standard of mental and physical well-being. Thus, a person's needs for food, shelter, medical care, protection, companionship and self-development are, at least in part, needs of this sort."

A third aspect of the minimalist view is a commitment to a permissive view of substitutability. The economist Robert Solow gives expression to this idea when he writes:

Goods and services can be substituted for one another. If you don't eat one species of fish, you can eat another species of fish. Resources are, to use a favorite word of economists, fungible in a certain sense. They can take the place of each other. That is extremely important because it suggests that we do not owe to the future any particular thing. There is no specific object that the goal of sustainability, the obligation of sustainability, requires us to leave untouched.


Clearly, assumptions about substitutability have a direct bearing on the question of whether we ought to be preserving some particular X in order to fulfill our sustainability-related obligations. While defenders of the minimalist view are not committed to the unlimited substitutability of (natural) goods and resources in practice, they are not opposed to this idea in principle. This commitment makes the view blind to some important normative considerations. The human flourishing account helps to illuminate these considerations, and I'll turn to this now.


II. THE HUMAN FLOURISHING ACCOUNT

As a focus for my discussion of the human flourishing account, I'll consider the recent work of John O'Neill, Alan Holland and Andrew Light. By articulating a normative basis for objecting to certain sorts of substitution, even if such substitutions are technically possible, the human flourishing account illuminates a significant potential shortcoming of the minimalist view.

The account developed by O'Neill et al. has two main elements. First, the authors defend a version of an objective state theory of well-being. The usual list of objective states or goods is endorsed (physical health, personal relations, autonomy, etc.), with one notable addition: the good of having a well-constituted relation with the nonhuman world. The relevant states are conceived as necessary constituents of a flourishing life, such that one is harmed if one lacks access to these states. Further, the authors suggest that the goods in question are disaggregated, meaning, a lot of one good cannot substitute for too little or none of another.

The second aspect of the account rests on an appeal to the importance of historical considerations for our thinking about value, human well-being and the natural (or partly natural) world. To value something in a historical way is to value it in virtue of its particular history, or because it is the product of processes of a certain sort. The contrast to a historical view is one that regards the value of an object as consisting solely in terms of its specific cluster of properties, where this cluster is understood in isolation from the history of the object or the processes by which it came about. O'Neill et al. focus on a subset of possible historical considerations characterized in terms of "narrative." Narrative considerations illuminate the ways in which particular environments are valuable because they embody the labors and history of individuals and communities. On this account, being able to perform one's identity in, or in relation to, narratively significant environments is partly constitutive of living a flourishing life. Put differently, one's life can be intimately bound up with a place in such a way that physical continuity with that place helps to "make sense" of one's life; conversely, alienation from a narratively significant place can diminish one's life. According to O'Neill et al., an objective state theory of well-being must be tempered by narrative considerations if we are to adequately appraise how a person's life goes.

The account offered by O'Neill et al. has clear implications for debates about sustainability. The authors argue that "what we need to pass on to future generations is a bundle of goods that can maintain welfare across the different dimensions of human life." These goods include the objective state components noted above, as well as the various life-support functions of the natural world that figure prominently in the minimalist view (i.e., as a precondition for satisfying basic needs). There are, in addition, two main respects in which O'Neill et al. offer something that goes beyond the minimalist view. First, the authors emphasize the social and environmental context in which human flourishing occurs. This emphasis is especially clear in the focus on narrative significance. Second, O'Neill et al. claim that we are obligated to maintain "particular environments" in order to fulfill our sustainability-related obligations. Both of these aspects have clear implications for how we should think about normatively permissible substitutions, some of which have a direct bearing on issues related to food justice. I will consider each of these aspects in turn.

Defenders of the minimalist view typically say very little about the social and environmental context in which welfare needs arise and are satisfied. To discuss well-being in abstraction from the broader context of supportive relationships, social practices and specific environments presents some notable hazards. Recall Solow's remark regarding the substitution of one species of fish for another. By endorsing a permissive view of substitutability, defenders of the minimalist account deny or obscure a number of normatively significant issues. To stay with the fish example, some communities around the globe are dependent on fish as an important source of food. Fish and fishing are also intimately tied up with their way of life. Due in large part to the shift toward industrial fishing and aquaculture since the 1970s, aquatic ecosystems have become degraded to the point that in some places traditional fishing communities can no longer catch the fish they need. To think, as Solow urges us to, that the main issue here is compensating people so they can find a suitable food substitute for fish is to miss a number of specific harms and injustices experienced by the people in question. Not only are the communities losing their access to an important food source, they are also, more generally, losing their ability to self-provision from nature in order to meet their needs. They may also be experiencing the destruction of their way of life. All of these losses may be very significant harms to the people involved. There may also be serious injustices, for example, if the people in question are (or have been) unfairly disadvantaged by a pattern of industrial development that they had little or no ability to influence the shape of. There is much more to say about such cases, but the main point is that Solow's claim "If you don't eat one species of fish, you can eat another species of fish" is naïve and very likely to lend support to policies that would generate, and in some cases further exacerbate, significant harm and injustice.

Perhaps a defender of a Solow-type view could say, in reply, that the minimalist view can account for these harms and injustices. That is, if the replacement of one species of fish with another goes hand in hand with the demise of traditional fishing practices, and if the demise of these practices makes the people in question worse off, then the substitution has resulted in a diminution of welfare. The problem is this reply is compatible with, and does not challenge, the view that the loss in question is one for which there could be adequate compensation. But this assumption about compensation is implausible. A way of life is not merely a way of meeting one's needs, or maintaining an abstract set of options for oneself and one's descendants. It involves a lived relation to particular environments and objects (such as fish). The relevant environments and objects are often suffused with meaning and cultural significance. To think that the people in question are — or in principle could be — adequately compensated so long as a substitute is found for fish, fishing and the specific environments (or environmental amenities) at issue, is to miss the specific type of harm and injustice caused, with its attendant losses. However, if the relevant individuals and communities actually regarded the compensation as acceptable, then this rejoinder would be considerably weakened. Though even in that case, we might still inquire whether people are accepting the compensation because they really have no alternative. There is, in any case, a whole set of considerations here — about the nature of harm, about injustice, about power — that the defender of a permissive view of substitutability obscures, or is apt to obscure.

These considerations pose a general problem for any endorsement of a permissive view of substitutability. Let me note three further points that emphasize the importance of the preceding discussion for our thinking about sustainability. First, harm and injustice, such as that caused by industrial aquaculture, is often a driver of environmental degradation. Second, I assume we need models or paradigms of ways of life that are sustainable. Indeed, one might think that an important aspect of our obligation to future generations is to provide them with models of how to live sustainably. When industrial aquaculture displaces traditional aquaculture (to stay with this case, though the point is a general one), this often destroys sustainable ways of life. This is bad, first and foremost, for those whose way of life is undermined. But it is also bad in the sense that we lose a paradigm from which people might learn how to live in particular places, meeting their needs and creating culture, while not destroying biodiversity, soil fertility and so on. More is at stake here than one might initially think.


(Continues...)

Excerpted from Just Food by J. M. Dieterle. Copyright © 2015 J. M. Dieterle. Excerpted by permission of Rowman & Littlefield International Ltd..
All rights reserved. No part of this excerpt may be reproduced or reprinted without permission in writing from the publisher.
Excerpts are provided by Dial-A-Book Inc. solely for the personal use of visitors to this web site.

Table of Contents

Acknowledgements / Introduction: J.M. Dieterle / Part I: Food Access / Chapter 1: J. Michael Scoville, "Framing Food Justice" / Chapter 2: Stephen Minister, "Food, Hunger, and Property" / Chapter 3: J.M. Dieterle, "Food Deserts and Lockean Property" / Chapter 4: Jennifer Szende, "Food Deserts, Justice, and the Distributive Paradigm" / Part II: Food Systems / Chapter 5: Ian Werkheiser, Shakara Tyler, and Paul Thompson, " Food Sovereignty: Two Conceptions of Food Justice" / Chapter 6: Mark Navin, "Food Sovereignty and Gender Justice: The Case of La Vía Campesina" / Chapter 7: Steve Tammelleo, "Food Policy, Mexican Migration, and Collective Responsibility" / Part III: Food and Gender / Chapter 8: Lori Watson, "Food is a Feminist Issue" / Chapter 9: Nancy M. Williams, "Meat Eating and Masculinity: A Foucauldian Analysis" / Chapter 10: Margaret Crouch, “Food, Film and Gender” / Part IV: Local Food / Chapter 11: Nancy E. Snow, "'Food Virtue': Can We Make Virtuous Food Choices?" / Chapter 12: Liz Goodnick, "Limits on Locavorism" / About the Authors / Bibliography
From the B&N Reads Blog

Customer Reviews