Game Theory and the Law / Edition 1

Game Theory and the Law / Edition 1

ISBN-10:
0674341112
ISBN-13:
9780674341111
Pub. Date:
09/01/1998
Publisher:
Harvard University Press
ISBN-10:
0674341112
ISBN-13:
9780674341111
Pub. Date:
09/01/1998
Publisher:
Harvard University Press
Game Theory and the Law / Edition 1

Game Theory and the Law / Edition 1

Paperback

$49.0 Current price is , Original price is $49.0. You
$49.00 
  • SHIP THIS ITEM
    Not Eligible for Free Shipping
  • PICK UP IN STORE
    Check Availability at Nearby Stores
  • SHIP THIS ITEM

    Temporarily Out of Stock Online

    Please check back later for updated availability.


Overview

This book is the first to apply the tools of game theory and information economics to advance our understanding of how laws work. Organized around the major solution concepts of game theory, it shows how such well known games as the prisoner’s dilemma, the battle of the sexes, beer-quiche, and the Rubinstein bargaining game can illuminate many different kinds of legal problems. Game Theory and the Law highlights the basic mechanisms at work and lays out a natural progression in the sophistication of the game concepts and legal problems considered.

Product Details

ISBN-13: 9780674341111
Publisher: Harvard University Press
Publication date: 09/01/1998
Edition description: New Edition
Pages: 344
Product dimensions: 6.12(w) x 9.25(h) x 0.75(d)

About the Author

Douglas G. Baird is Harry A. Bigelow Distinguished Service Professor of Law at the University of Chicago Law School.

Robert H. Gertner is Professor of Economics and Strategy at the University of Chicago.

Randal C. Picker is Paul and Theo Leffmann Professor of Law at the University of Chicago.

Read an Excerpt

Pages 180 - 182

...profit-maximizers or care only about money, but rather that they act in a way that is sensible for them given their own tastes and predilections. This assumption may not always hold in an individual case, because people at times act in ways that are inconsistent and self-destructive. In general, however, people make the best decisions they can, given their beliefs about what others will do. (p. 11)
They offer solid cautionary advice (especially in an extended discussion in chapter six) about the care necessary to avoid using the wrong models to analyze subtle social situations. (How many of us have wondered whether the world really is one big Prisoner's Dilemma game?) Finally, throughout their analysis they maintain a realistic view of the assumptions about the world to which we commit ourselves when we employ game-theoretic solution concepts, assumptions that may lead us to draw false inferences about the effects of legal rules on strategic behavior. In discussing the move from a less restrictive to a more restrictive solution concept, the authors note that "we must assume more about what individuals know and more about how they believe others will act. The more we have to make such assumptions, the less certain we can be that our model will accurately predict the way individuals behave." (p. 13)
Having set forth their understanding of the strengths and weaknesses of game-theoretic analysis in their early discussion, Baird, Gertner and Picker proceed in the course of the book to make a powerful case for the value of the approach. To give an adequate sense of the sheer breadth of their coverage, I will merely outline the issues -- both game-theoretic and legal -- that they address in their eight chapters. In the first chapter they present the basic assumptions of strategic behavior and introduce static games and their basic solution concepts (including Nash); they discuss tort laws governing negligence and the duty of due care. In the second chapter they incorporate time into the analysis and begin a consideration of extensive form games (including an exceptionally clear and informative explication of the subgame perfect solution concept); they demonstrate the relevance of models of ongoing interactions in the areas of antitrust law and debtor-creditor relations. In chapters three and four they introduce the complexity of incomplete information, the realistic assumption that there is important information relevant to the social interaction that is unknown to either one or both of the actors. The authors call incomplete information "the central problem in game theory and the law." (p. 2) From a strategic perspective they develop the issues of unraveling, signaling, screening, the crucial role of beliefs in games of incomplete information and the basic incomplete information solution concept, perfect Bayesian equilibrium, and some of its refinements; from a legal perspective the authors show how incomplete information influences the effect of legal rules in such areas as plant closing laws, parental leave provisions, disclosure laws, inquiry limits (including a provocative discussion of the Americans with Disabilities Act) and various laws that govern contracts that envision future renegotiations. In chapters five and six they consider a set of issues related to problems of collective action and cooperative behavior. The game theoretic issues included in these chapters include repeated games, the problem of multiple equilibria, the folk theorem, the effect of reputation and mechanism design; the legal issues include the Statute of Frauds and antitrust regulations governing predatory pricing and tacit collusion. In the last two chapters the authors introduce distributional considerations including an explication of non-cooperative bargaining theory (both the classic Rubenstein model and various models which incorporate assumptions of incomplete information); then they demonstrate the value of these models for understanding bankruptcy law (including the provisions governing automatic stays and the new value exception), labor law (restrictions on hiring permanent replacement workers) and rules of civil procedure (including provisions covering pre-trial discovery procedures and rules dictating the structure of hearings and trials.)
But even more than through their comprehensiveness, the authors' case for the value of game theory is made through the creativity of their analysis. To highlight this creativity, I will briefly discuss two examples of the significant insights which they offer. First, as I have previously stated, the problems related to information are, in the minds of the authors, fundamental to law. They emphasize the importance of the distinction between verifiable and nonverifiable information. Through their analysis of social interactions that are characterized by these different types of information, they demonstrate one of the major insights of their analysis: legal rules intended to affect the communication of private information (that is, information known to only some of the actors involved in an interaction) will have different effects depending on whether or not the information is verifiable (by either the other actors or a court.) An especially striking feature of this insight is captured in their claim "[t]o understand the effects of a legal rule, we must pay attention to the way it affects not only actions that the parties actually take, but also actions that they would not have taken even in the absence of a legal rule." (p. 156) Here the value of the use of game theory is most telling because this particular insight is explicitly derived from the implications of the game-theoretic concept of off-the - equilibrium path beliefs (basically, the idea that people are often affected in how they will act by their expectations of what those with whom they interact will do if they themselves were to act differently.) Through a set of legal examples analyzed by a simple model of incomplete information, the authors show that the law can influence behavior by establishing rules that prohibit behavior that the actors would not do even if the rule was not in place. For example, in a situation in which employers are known to discriminate against disabled job applicants, the authors find that the equilibrium outcome is that disabled applicants misrepresent their disabilities and thus employers treat all applicants similarly. When the authors introduce a rule that prohibits discrimination based on disability, the equilibrium outcome changes to one in which the disabled workers reveal their disabilities and the employer adopts a work plan that differs for disabled and nondisabled workers and which produces a superior outcome for both workers and the employer. Thus, a rule that prohibits an action that the employer would not even take if the actors were being strategically rational nonetheless produces a change in behavior that is socially optimal.
Second, the authors show how game-theoretic analysis can provide insights into how we might make mistakes in our analysis of the effects of legal rules. Their analysis shows that studies of the effects of discovery rules on civil litigation will misconstrue those effects if they focus merely on the cases that go to trial. The authors demonstrate a selection bias in such a study sample. By analyzing the strategic effects of discovery rules on pre-trial negotiations, the authors show that some discovery rules have the effect of causing those parties who are most likely to be liable to settle their cases before trial, thus selecting out those cases most likely to result in a judgment for the plaintiff. Because of this pre-trial effect, the cases that do actually go to trial are disproportionately those most likely to lead to a judgment for defendants (because people who know that they are not liable are the ones least likely to accept a settlement offer.) If analysts were to base their investigation of rules of civil procedure merely on the cases that go to trial and judgment, they would, on the authors' analysis, fail to capture important effects of these rules. This selection bias is clarified by the use of a simple game-theoretic model of litigation.
These are merely two examples from a wealth of insights offered by Baird, Gertner and Picker. The persuasiveness of their general argument for the utility of game theory derives from a combination of the power of their insights along with the sensibility of their analysis. The book is written in a clear, concise and interesting manner. Its bibliographic references render it a source book for additional research in both game theory and law. This is a book that should be read by scholars of law in particular and scholars of political behavior in general. One of the best compliments that I can give it is that it would also be a profitable investment for those who focus primarily on formal models of strategic behavior and games.

Table of Contents

  • Preface
  • Introduction: Understanding Strategic Behavior

    • Bibliographic Notes


  • Simultaneous Decisionmaking and the Normal Form Game

    • The Normal Form Game
    • Using Different Games to Compare Legal Regimes
    • The Nash Equilibrium
    • Civil Liability, Accident Law, and Strategic Behavior
    • Legal Rules and the Idea of Strict Dominance
    • Collective Action Problems and the Two-by-Two Game
    • The Problem of Multiple Nash Equilibria
    • Summary
    • Bibliographic Notes


  • Dynamic Interaction and the Extensive Form Game

    • The Extensive Form Game and Backwards Induction
    • A Dynamic Model of Preemption and Strategic Commitment
    • Subgame Perfection
    • Summary
    • Bibliographic Notes


  • Information Revelation, Disclosure Laws, and Renegotiation

    • Incorporating Beliefs into the Solution Concept
    • The Perfect Bayesian Equilibrium Solution Concept
    • Verifiable Information, Voluntary Disclosure, and the Unraveling Result
    • Disclosure Laws and the Limits of Unraveling
    • Observable Information, Norms, and the Problem of Renegotiation
    • Optimal Incentives and the Need for Renegotiation
    • Limiting the Ability of Parties to Renegotiate
    • Summary
    • Bibliographic Notes


  • Signaling, Screening, and Nonverifiable Information

    • Signaling and Screening
    • Modeling Nonverifiable Information
    • Signals and the Effects of Legal Rules
    • Information Revelation and Contract Default Rules
    • Screening and the Role of Legal Rules
    • Summary
    • Bibliographic Notes


  • Reputation and Repeated Games

    • Backwards Induction and Its Limits
    • Infinitely Repeated Games, Tacit Collusion, and Folk Theorems
    • Reputation, Predation, and Cooperation
    • Summary
    • Bibliographic Notes


  • Collective Action, Embedded Games, and the Limits of Simple Models

    • Collective Action and the Role of Law
    • Embedded Games
    • Understanding the Structure of Large Games
    • Collective Action and Private Information
    • Collective Action Problems in Sequential Decisionmaking
    • Herd Behavior
    • Summary
    • Bibliographic Notes


  • Noncooperative Bargaining

    • Modeling the Division of Gains from Trade
    • Legal Rules as Exit Options
    • Bargaining and Corporate Reorganizations
    • Collective Bargaining and Exit Options
    • Summary
    • Bibliographic Notes


  • Bargaining and Information

    • Basic Models of the Litigation Process
    • Modeling Separate Trials for Liability and Damages
    • Information and Selection Bias
    • Discovery Rules and Verifiable Information
    • Summary
    • Bibliographic Notes


  • Conclusion: Information and the Limits of Law
  • Notes
  • References
  • Glossary
  • Index

What People are Saying About This

Daniel A. Farber

Game Theory and the Law promises to be the definitive guide to the field. It provides a highly sophisticated yet exceptionally clear explanation of game theory, with a host of applications to legal issues. The authors have not only synthesized the existing scholarship, but also created the foundation for the next generation of research in law and economics."
Daniel A. Farber, University of Minnesota Law School

From the B&N Reads Blog

Customer Reviews