After Heidegger?

After Heidegger?

After Heidegger?

After Heidegger?

eBook

$56.00 

Available on Compatible NOOK devices, the free NOOK App and in My Digital Library.
WANT A NOOK?  Explore Now

Related collections and offers

LEND ME® See Details

Overview

This unique volume collects more than 30 new essays by prominent scholars on what remains philosophically provocative in Heidegger’s thought. His writings continue to invite analysis and application — ut, particularly in the light of his political affiliations, they must also be critiqued. Philosophy today takes place after Heidegger in that his views should not be accepted naively, and there are new issues that he did not address — but also in that we continue to think in the wake of important questions that he raised.

The contributors to this volume ask questions such as:
- What does it mean to think “after” Heidegger?
- What is valuable in his early work on finite existence, and in his early and late phenomenology?
- What is the root of his political errors? Are there still elements in his thought that can yield helpful political insights?
- Should we emulate his turn toward “releasement”?
- Can he help us understand the postmodern condition?

Readers will find thought-provoking echoes and points of contention among these engaging and lively essays.

Product Details

ISBN-13: 9781786604873
Publisher: Rowman & Littlefield Publishers, Inc.
Publication date: 11/08/2017
Series: New Heidegger Research
Sold by: Barnes & Noble
Format: eBook
Pages: 392
File size: 2 MB
Age Range: 18 Years

About the Author


Gregory Fried is Professor of Philosophy at Suffolk University. With Richard Polt he has translated Heidegger’s Introduction to Metaphysics and Being and Truth, and edited A Companion to Heidegger’s “Introduction to Metaphysics” and Nature, History, State: 1933-1934.

Richard Polt is Professor of Philosophy at Xavier University. With Gregory Fried he has translated Heidegger’s Introduction to Metaphysics and Being and Truth, and edited A Companion to Heidegger’s “Introduction to Metaphysics” and Nature, History, State: 1933-1934.

Read an Excerpt

CHAPTER 1

Heidegger: Enduring Questions

Drew A. Hyland

I want to begin this short chapter by reaffirming the guiding assumption articulated by our two editors, that despite Heidegger's deplorable political history, there is much, very much, philosophic work that remains to be done in response to his work. As I shall argue, the question of the relation between a philosopher's political life (in the broadest sense of that phrase) and his or her philosophical writing is itself a philosophical issue, and certainly one not adequately addressed by rejecting Heidegger as a philosopher or relegating his work to the section of our libraries on the history of Nazism.

The editors have asked what are some of the most pressing and challenging issues for philosophy after — that is, in the philosophical wake of — Heidegger. I want to briefly discuss three issues: first, the centrality of the question as the core philosophical stance and speech act in Heidegger; second, and related, Heidegger's development of the distinction between "calculative" and "meditative" thinking and his call to preserve meditative thinking under the threat of the total dominance of calculative thinking; and third, as mentioned earlier, the question of the relation between a philosopher's thinking and the life lived, particularly if that philosophical thinking includes an affirmation of thinking as "beyond good and evil." I turn first to the question of the question.

Book after book of Heidegger's is titled as a question, and as if to underline the importance of this, Heidegger presses the limits of syntax to find alternative ways to formulate the question asked in his titles. Thus we find Die Frage nach dem Ding (The Question of the Thing), "Zur Seinsfrage" (On the Question of Being), Was heißt Denken? (What Is Called Thinking?), Was ist das, die Philosophie? (What Is Philosophy?), Was ist Metaphysik? (What Is Metaphysics?), among others. Even Sein und Zeit (Being and Time), though not titled as a question, makes it clear from the beginning that the whole purpose of this groundbreaking book is to raise the question of the meaning of Being. And of course, none of Heidegger's texts ask the question of the title and then answer it in the book! The point of Heidegger's thinking, that is, is not to "answer" this or that question but rather to deepen the question-worthiness of the issue at hand. One might say that the questions Heidegger asks call not for answers but for responses, where the difference would be that answers seek for a kind of closure on a given issue, whereas responses seek rather to open up that issue, to deepen our sensitivity to its nuances of meaning. In a world increasingly dominated by the kind of thinking that demands answers (more on this presently), Heidegger's thought-path tries to keep alive a kind of thinking that attempts to dwell — and it will demand a dwelling — in what we might call the open of the question. That phrase hints at an even larger issue: for the call for questioning as the fundamental speech act of philosophy occurs as a response to an open, and an open which, if Heidegger is right, will ever remain open (even if always also partially hidden), not one that will be "closed" or "solved" by any future thinker. Throughout his career, Heidegger names this open with various provocative words: Being, event of appropriation (Ereignis), that-which-regions (das Gegnet), clearing (die Lichtung), and the Open. But for me, what remains "the same" through these various pathways is what Heidegger sees as the appropriate response to them, which remains, always, questioning. One might say that whereas for almost all of philosophy since Descartes, the fundamental philosophic speech act has been the assertion — the assertion of "truths," of theories, of proofs, of conclusions, of refutations — Heidegger, by contrast, is trying to preserve for philosophy the fundamentality of that speech act which is questioning.

In this, it strikes me that there is a deep kinship with a thinker that Heidegger himself might be uncomfortable acknowledging as akin: the Platonic Socrates, and in particular, Socrates's sustaining of aporia as his very stance of philosophy. In Plato's Apology, at the very end of his life, Socrates characterizes his "human wisdom" precisely as his aporia, his recognition that he is not wise, a recognition whose appropriate response is always that of questioning. To be sure, in many dialogues, read superficially, Socrates seems to be seeking closure, to want a "definition" of courage, or friendship, or sophrosyne, or beauty, or knowledge itself. But we must note — and surely Plato wanted us to note this — that these attempted definitions, these apparent attempts at the closure of full knowledge, always fail. Do the dialogues therefore fail? Not at all! The dialogues succeed, succeed in opening up for us the question-worthiness of the issue at hand, help us to deepen our understanding of the call of the question concerning courage, or friendship, or knowledge. Socrates succeeds, moreover, not in reducing his interlocutors and us, Plato's readers, to aporia, but in raising them up to the achievement of aporia. In this affirmation of aporia and its questioning, Heidegger will always be a Socratic. And in a world that increasingly demands answers, a world that increasingly understands questions as a kind of weakness to be overcome, Heidegger seeks to sustain for us a recognition of the power of the question and of the open that gives us the question. One task for philosophy after Heidegger, surely, is to continue cultivating this openness, to sustain the priority of the question for philosophy and for human living.

Second, and intimately related to this, is the preservation of what Heidegger calls in his "Memorial Address" to the citizens of Messkirch "meditative thinking," or, in his "Conversation on a Country Path," "releasement," or sometimes simply "thinking." The general point is this: Heidegger distinguishes between two basic kinds of thinking. The first is the one we use all the time in our "pragmatic" activities of life. In the "Memorial Address" he calls it "calculative thinking" (rechnendes Denken). It is characterized by being goal oriented, by its emphasis on order, system, and problem solving. Logic and mathematics are perhaps the paradigms of calculative thinking, though one gets the impression that almost all goal-oriented or problem-solving thinking counts as calculative. The second kind of thinking, "meditative" thinking, "releasement," or just "thinking," is quite different. Understandably, it is less precisely defined, since it is characterized not by logic, an urge to system, or a goal-oriented striving for closure on a given issue, but on an openness, yet not an openness to a specific, pre-calculated end. In the "Memorial Address" Heidegger calls this "openness to the mystery." In the "Conversation on a Country Path" he speaks of it as "releasement" (Gelassenheit), a kind of "waiting" but not an "awaiting," where the difference is that "awaiting" is an expectation of some specific happening, whereas "waiting" remains open to what may eventuate. It is in this openness that the kinship with questioning becomes clear. Both the questioning he espouses and the "releasement" he commends are characterized by a certain openness, not a predetermining of outcomes or even expecting certain outcomes. The English phrase "to hold open to question," taken in its full sense, captures something of what Heidegger intends by this mode of thinking.

It must be emphasized that there is nothing in principle wrong with calculative thinking. To the contrary, it is imperative for "getting along" in the world, and the last thing that Heidegger would ask is that we do without it. The problem he sees is that particularly and increasingly in our epoch, calculative thinking threatens to become the only acceptable mode of thinking, indeed to be regarded as thinking itself. Meditative thinking, releasement, may be lost as a human possibility as the emphasis on technology, on calculation, on statistical analysis, takes over our lives more and more. The point of Heidegger's drawing the distinction is to keep alive the very possibility of this other thinking, this thinking that, Heidegger seems to hold, in the end is what makes us human, for one fine day we shall learn that machines are much better than we are at calculative thinking.

I think that in this distinction Heidegger identifies a very important issue in the modern epoch. The dominance of technology, what might be regarded as the triumph of calculative thinking, is all around us. Even in the intellectual world in which we academics live, we see its dominance everywhere. We must all "document" our teaching ability through "measures" often called "learning assessment." The legitimacy of traditional "liberal arts" education is being increasingly questioned precisely because its "practical" value is not obvious to all. In the "discipline" (itself a calculative word) of philosophy, the dominant understanding of philosophy today is called "analytic" philosophy, a movement whose explicit aim is to "solve philosophical problems." Heidegger's challenge in this regard is therefore ever more important and ever more difficult: how do we preserve that manifestly less "practical," less goal-oriented, less closure-achieving thinking in an age where those very values are increasingly dominant? One "calculative" issue much discussed today has to do with the fact that machines — computers in particular — are increasingly capable of doing all the calculative thinking that we humans do, only more accurately and faster. Is Heidegger then perhaps right that it is this "other" thinking that would make and keep us human?

I turn to the third issue I want to address by noting that so far as I can see, not a thing I have discussed so far could be plausibly associated with a particular political standpoint, much less with the specific political standpoint which Heidegger himself took at least in the early 1930s, that of Nazism. Even less would questioning and meditative thinking have anything to do with anti-Semitism, a vice in which Heidegger also indulged. Yet questioning and this "released" mode of thinking are important and sustained themes in Heidegger's thought-path. They both therefore stand as manifest refutations of any claim that Heidegger's thinking is "through and through" Nazistic or anti-Semitic. Such a claim is nonsense.

Nevertheless, Heidegger was a Nazi, at least for a while, and an antiSemite, and therefore the question must be raised: what are we to make of the fact that one of the greatest philosophers of the twentieth century was an enthusiastic advocate of what was surely the most diabolic political regime of that century? And we must also note that to ask this very question is to raise a philosophical issue.

As indicated earlier, the issue here should not be something like "Was Heidegger really a Nazi and anti-Semite, is his published thinking Nazistic and anti-Semitic, and therefore should we stop taking him seriously as a philosopher?" The answers to these questions are too easy: yes, he was, at least for a while, a Nazi and anti-Semite. No, his philosophic thinking is neither Nazistic nor anti-Semitic, at least not in any comprehensive sense. So, no, his work remains genuinely and profoundly philosophic and should continue to be taken seriously by serious philosophers. We can and should still wonder and be troubled by the few now notorious references to the "inner truth and greatness" of Nazism and the "Jewification" of culture, but doing so, I think, should not allow us to miss the genuinely philosophical issue at stake in this sorry situation.

The real issue for me has always been not "was Heidegger a Nazi or anti-Semite?" or "is his philosophy Nazistic or anti-Semitic?" both of which have been easily answered earlier, but rather this: why was there apparently nothing in his philosophy, nothing in his thinking, that enabled him, no, that demanded of him, to say "No!" to anything like the Nazis or anti-Semitism? To raise this question is to raise a most serious issue about the efficacy of Heidegger's thought-project as a whole. But, as I shall argue, it raises that issue not just about Heidegger but about much of twentieth-century philosophy.

Considerations such as these lead me to suggest a different and in a way more demanding formulation of the question of Heidegger's involvement with Nazism: was there anything in his philosophy that should have led Heidegger to reject National Socialism and its accompanying anti-Semitism, even though we know that it did not? And if not, what are we to make of a philosophic view that contains nothing within it that might call for the rejection of a political position as diabolical as Nazism?

I suggest that there is nothing in Heidegger's thought that would have forbidden the affirmation of Nazism because from at least the time of Being and Time (1927), Heidegger claimed that all questions of ethics and politics were "ontic" questions of "everydayness," whereas his thought, concerned always with the question of Being, was "ontological" and therefore prior to and independent of questions of ethics and politics. In Being and Time, developing the thesis that values are "ontic" and even "present-at-hand," that is, treated as objective or quasi-objective "things" in the world, Heidegger argues that "these value characters themselves are rather just ontical characteristics of those entities which have the kind of Being possessed by things" (MR 132). Much later in the work, in the development of his notion of ontological "guilt," and insisting that we must not think of guilt within the usual, "ontic" parameters of evil or good, he adds that "Just as the bonum and its privatio have the same ontological origin in the ontology of the present-at-hand, this ontology also applies to the idea of 'value,' which has been abstracted from these."

(Continues…)



Excerpted from "After Heidegger?"
by .
Copyright © 2018 Gregory Fried and Richard Polt.
Excerpted by permission of Rowman & Littlefield International, Ltd..
All rights reserved. No part of this excerpt may be reproduced or reprinted without permission in writing from the publisher.
Excerpts are provided by Dial-A-Book Inc. solely for the personal use of visitors to this web site.

Table of Contents

Editors’ Introduction / Part I: Overviews / 1.Heidegger: Enduring Questions, Drew Hyland / 2. On Beyond Heidegger, Gregory Fried / 3. In Heidegger’s Wake, Daniel Dahlstrom / 4. The Critical Appropriation of Heidegger’s Philosophy, Peter Gordon / Part II: After the Black Notebooks / 5. What is Left of Heidegger, Donatella Di Cesare / 6. Thinking-Time: Or, Why Do “We” Ask About the Future of Heidegger’s Thinking? Peter Trawny / 7. Getting Ourselves on the Hook, Julia Ireland / 8. Aftermath, Babette Babich / Part III: Politics and Ethics / 9. Heidegger: Beyond Anti-Semitism and Seinsgeschichte, John McCumber / 10. Ecce Homo/Ecce Cogitatio: On Heidegger’s Politics and Philosophy, Lawrence Hatab / / 11. Thought, Action and History: Rethinking Revolution After Heidegger, Arun Iyer / 12. Ethics After Heidegger, Dennis Schmidt / Part IV: Life and Existence / 13. Becoming Hermeneutical Before Being Philosophical, Robert Schaff / 14. The Strangeness of Life in Heidegger’s Philosophy, Eric Nelson / 15. Alienation and Belongingness, Kevin Aho and Charles Guignon / 16. Being at Issue, Richard Polt / 17. Heidegger’s Schematizations, Lee Braver / 18.Dasein: From Existential Situation to Appropriation in the Event, Theodore Kisiel / Part V: Phenomenology and Ontology / 19. Of Paths and Method: Heidegger as a Phenomenologist, Steven Crowell / 20. But What Comes Before the “After”? Thomas Sheehan / 21. Still, the Unrest of the Question of Being, Katherine Withy / 22. What is the Meaning of the Meaning of Being? Simon Critchley / 23. The Future of Thought: Of a Phenomenology of the Inapparent, François Raffoul / Part VI: Thinking with Late Heidegger/ 24. On the Essence and Concept of Ereignis: From Technē to Technicity, William McNeill / 25. Learning to See Otherwise: The Transformative Appropriation of Vision, David Kleinberg-Levin / 26. On the Meaning and Possibility of Thought, Miguel de Beistegui / 27. Clearing and Space: Thinking with Heidegger and Beyond, Günter Figal / 28. Thinking Embodied Time-Spaces with and Beyond Heidegger, Daniela Vallega-Neu / 29. The Appeal of Things: Ethics and Relation, Andrew Mitchell / 30. Overcoming the Subjectivisms of Our Age, Richard Capobianco / Part VII: Openings to Others /31. Thinking Heidegger’s Postmodern Unthought, Iain Thomson / 32. East-West Dialogue after Heidegger, Bret Davis / 33. This is not a Love Story: Robot Girl and das Rettende after Heidegger, Trish Glazebrook / About the Contributors / Index
From the B&N Reads Blog

Customer Reviews